Contents

Preface

Acknowledgements

1 An Analysis of Counterfactuals

1.1 Introduction

1.2 Strict Conditionals

1.3 Variably Strict Conditionals

1.4 The Limit Assumption

1.5 ‘Might’ Counterfactuals and Outer Modalities

1.6 Impossible Antecedents

1.7 True Antecedents

1.8 Counterfactual Fallacies

1.9 Potentialities

2. Reformulations

2.1 Multiple Modalities

2.2 Propositional Quantification

2.3 Comparative Similarity

2.4 Similarity Measures

2.5 Comparative Possibility

2.6 Cotenability

2.7 Selection Functions

2.8 The Selection Operator

3. Comparisons

3.1 The Metalinguistic Theory: Implicit Premises

3.2 The Metalinguistic Theory: Factual Premises

3.3 The Metalinguistic Theory: Laws of Nature

3.4 Stalnakefs Theory

4. Foundations

4.1 Possible Worlds

4.2 Similarity

5. ANALOGIES

5.1 Conditional Obligation

5.2 ‘When Next’ and ‘When Last’

5.3 Contextually Definite Descriptions

6. LOGICS

6.1 Completeness Results

6.2 Decidability Results

6.3 Derived hlodal Logics

Appendix: Related Writings by David Lewis

Index

IN MEMORY OF RICHARD MONTAGUE

Preface

The principal changes in this revised printing are in Section 6.1, where I have corrected two major errors in my discussion of completeness results for the V-logics. Both of them were spotted by Erik C. W. Krabbe in 1976. I am most grateful to him for finding the trouble, and also for very helpful correspondence about alternative methods of repair. One error was in my construction of the canonical basis on pages 127–130: I falsely claimed that the set of co-spheres of cuts around a given index would be closed under unions.* In order to ensure such closure, it is necessary to construct the canonical basis differently. The other was in the axiom system for VC given on page 132. I left out the rule of Interchange of Logical Equivalents; however I tacitly appealed to this rule in proving completeness, so my proof did not apply to the axiom system I had given.

In addition I have corrected minor errors on pages 35, 55 and 129, also spotted by Krabbe; removed misprints; and brought some references up to date.

I have had more to say about counterfactuals and related matters. These further thoughts might appropriately have been added to this book; but since they are to be found elsewhere, I have been content to add an appendix giving citations and abstracts.

David Lewis
1986

* Erik C. W. Krabbe, ‘Note on a Completeness Theorem in the Theory of Counterfactuals’, Journal of Philosophical Logic 7 (1978): 91–93.

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Kit Fine, Hans Kamp, David Kaplan, Richard Montague, J. Howard Sobel, Robert Stalnaker, Richmond Thomason, and many other friends and colleagues for encouragement and for valuable discussions about counterfactuals over the last five years.

I am grateful also to the American Council of Learned Societies for financial assistance, and to Saint Catherine’s College, Oxford, for hospitality, during the year when most of this book was written.

David Lewis

Princeton, June 1972

1. An Analysis of Counterfactuals

1.1 Introduction

If kangaroos had no tails, they would topple over’ seems to me to mean something like this: in any possible state of affairs in which kangaroos have no tails, and which resembles our actual state of affairs as much as kangaroos having no tails permits it to, the kangaroos topple over. I shall give a general analysis of counterfactual conditionals along these lines.

My methods are those of much recent work in possible-world semantics for intensional logic.* I shall introduce a pair of counterfactual conditional operators intended to correspond to the various counterfactual conditional constructions of ordinary language; and I shall interpret these operators by saying how the truth value at a given possible world of a counterfactual conditional is to depend on the truth values at various possible worlds of its antecedent and consequent.

Counterfactuals are notoriously vague. That does not mean that we cannot give a clear account of their truth conditions. It does mean that such an account must either be stated in vague terms—which does not mean ill-understood terms—or be made relative to some parameter that is fixed only within rough limits on any given occasion of language use. It is to be hoped that this imperfectly fixed parameter is a familiar one that we would be stuck with whether or not we used it in the analysis of counterfactuals; and so it will be. It will be a relation of comparative similarity.

Let us employ a language containing these two counterfactual conditional operators:

read as ‘If it were the case that ___, then it would be the case that…’, and

read as ‘If it were the case that ___, then it might be the case that...’.For instance, the two sentences below would be symbolized as shown.

If Otto behaved himself, he would be ignored.

Otto behaves himself Otto is ignored

If Otto were ignored, he might behave himself.

Otto is ignored Otto behaves himself

There is to be no prohibition against embedding counterfactual conditionals within other counterfactual conditionals. A sentence of such a form as this.

will be perfectly well formed and will be assigned truth conditions, although doubtless it would be such a confusing sentence that we never would have occasion to utter it.

The two counterfactual operators are to be interdefinable as follows.

Thus we can take either one as primitive. Its interpretation determines the interpretation of the other. I shall take the ‘would’ counterfactual as primitive.

Other operators can be introduced into our language by definition in terms of the counterfactual operators, and it will prove useful to do so. Certain modal operators will be thus introduced in Sections 1.5 and 1.7; modified versions of the counterfactual in Section 1.6; and ‘comparative possibility’ operators in Section 2.5.

My official English readings of my counterfactual operators must be taken with a good deal of caution. First, I do not intend that they should interfere, as the counterfactual constructions of English sometimes do, with the tenses of the antecedent and consequent. My official reading of the sentence

We were finished packing Monday night we departed Tuesday morning

comes out as a sentence obscure in meaning and of doubtful grammatically:

If it were the case that we were finished packing Monday night, then it would be the case that we departed Tuesday morning.

In the correct reading, the subjunctive ‘were’ of the counterfactual construction and the temporal ‘were’ of the antecedent are transformationally combined into a past subjunctive:

If we had been finished packing Monday night, then we would have departed Tuesday morning.

Second, the ‘If it were the case that___’ of my official reading of is not meant to imply that it is not the case that___. Counterfactuals with true antecedents—counterfactuals that are not counterfactual—are not automatically false, nor do they lack truth value. This stipulation does not seem to me at all artificial. Granted, the counterfactual constructions of English do carry some sort of presupposition that the antecedent is false. It is some sort of mistake to use them unless the speaker does take the antecedent to be false, and some sort of mishap to use them when the speaker wrongly takes the antecedent to be false. But there is no reason to suppose that every sort of presupposition failure must produce automatic falsity or a truth-value gap. Some or all sorts of presupposition, and in particular the presupposition that the antecedent of a counterfactual is false, may be mere matters of conversational implicature, without any effect on truth conditions. Though it is difficult to find out the truth conditions of counterfactuals with true antecedents, since they would be asserted only by mistake, we will see later (in Section 1.7) how this may be done.

You may justly complain, therefore, that my title ‘Counterfactuals’ is too narrow for my subject. I agree, but I know no better. I cannot claim to be giving a theory of conditionals in general. As Ernest Adams has observed,* the first conditional below is probably true, but the second may very well be false. (Change the example if you are not a Warrenite.)

If Oswald did not kill Kennedy, then someone else did.

If Oswald had not killed Kennedy, then someone else would have.

Therefore there really are two different sorts of conditional; not a single conditional that can appear as indicative or as counterfactual depending on the speaker’s opinion about the truth of the antecedent.

The title ‘Subjunctive Conditionals’ would not have delineated my subject properly. For one thing, there are shortened counterfactual conditionals like ‘No Hitler, no A-bomb’ that have no subjunctives except in their—still all-too-hypothetical—deep structure. More important, there are subjunctive conditionals pertaining to the future, like ‘ If our ground troops entered Laos next year, there would be trouble’ that appear to have the truth conditions of indicative conditionals, rather than of the counterfactual conditionals I shall be considering.*

1.2 Strict Conditionals

We shall see that the counterfactual cannot be any strict conditional. Since it turns out to be something not too different, however, let us set the stage by reviewing the interpretation of strict conditionals in the usual possible-world semantics for modality. Generally speaking, a strict conditional is a material conditional preceded by some sort of necessity operator:

With every necessity operator there is paired its dual possibility operator . The two are interdefinable:

If we like, we can rewrite the strict conditional using the possibility operator:

Or we could introduce a primitive strict conditional arrow or hook, and define the necessity and possibility operators from that. ‡

A necessity operator, in general, is an operator that acts like a restricted universal quantifier over possible worlds. Necessity of a certain sort is truth at all possible worlds that satisfy a certain restriction. We call these worlds accessible, meaning thereby simply that they satisfy the restriction associated with the sort of necessity under consideration. Necessity is truth at all accessible worlds, and different sorts of necessity correspond to different accessibility restrictions. A possibility operator, likewise, is an operator that acts like a restricted existential quantifier over worlds. Possibility is truth at some accessible world, and the accessibility restriction imposed depends on the sort of possibility under consideration. If a necessity operator and a possibility operator correspond to the same accessibility restriction on the worlds quantified over, then they will be a dual, interdefinable pair.

In the case of physical necessity, for instance, we have this restriction: the accessible worlds are those where the actual laws of nature hold true. Physical necessity is truth at all worlds where those laws hold true; physical possibility is truth at some worlds where those laws hold true.

In the case of physical necessity, which possible worlds are admitted as accessible depends on what the actual laws of nature happen to be. The restriction will be different From The Standpoint Of worlds with different laws of nature. Let i and j be worlds with different laws of nature, and let k be a world where the laws of i hold true but the different laws of j are violated. From the standpoint of i, k is an accessible world; from the standpoint of j it is not. Accessibility is in this case—and most cases—a relative matter. It is the custom, therefore, to think of accessibility as a relation between worlds: we say that k is accessible from i, but k is not accessible from j. We say also that i stands to k, but j does not stand to k, in the accessibility relation for physical necessity and possibility.

In general: to a necessity operator or a possibility operator there corresponds an accessibility relation. The appropriate accessibility relation serves to restrict quantification over worlds in giving the truth conditions for or . For any possible world i and sentence ϕ, the sentence ϕ is true at the world i if and only if, for every world j such that j is accessible from i, ϕ is true at j. Likewise ϕ is true at i if and only if, for some world j such that j is accessible from i, ϕ is true at j. More concisely: ϕ is true at i if and only if φ is true at every world accessible from i; ϕ is true at i if and only if ϕ is true at some world accessible from i. It follows that the strict conditional (ϕψ) is true at i if and only if, for every world j such that j is accessible from i, the material conditional ϕψ is true at j; that is, if and only if, for every world j such that j is accessible from i and ϕ is true at j, ψ is true at j. More concisely: (ϕ ⊃ $ ψ) is true at i if and only if ψ is true at every accessible ϕ-world. (‘ϕ-world‘, of course, abbreviates ‘world at which ϕ is true‘, and likewise for parallel formations.)

FIGURE 1

It suits my purposes better not to use the customary accessibility relations, but instead to adopt a slightly different—but obviously equivalent—formulation. Corresponding to a necessity operator , or a possibility operator , or a kind of strict conditional, let us have an assignment to each world i of a set Si of worlds, called the sphere of accessibility around i and regarded as the set of worlds accessible from i.* The assignment of spheres to worlds may be called the accessibility assignment corresponding to the modal operator. It is used to give the truth conditions for modal sentences as follows.

A sentence ϕ is true at a world i if and only if ϕ is true throughout the sphere of accessibility Si around i (as shown in Figure 1(A)).

A sentence ϕ is true at a world i if and only if ϕ is true somewhere in the sphere Si (as shown in Figure 1(B)).

A strict conditional sentence (ϕψ) is true at i if and only if ϕψ is true throughout the sphere Si; that is, if and only if ψ is true at every ϕ-world in Si (as shown in Figure 1(C)).

Let us consider various examples of accessibility assignments for various sorts of necessity, with particular attention to the corresponding strict conditionals.

Corresponding to logical necessity, and the logical strict conditional, we assign to each world i as its sphere of accessibility Si the set of all possible worlds. Thus the logical strict conditional (ϕψ) is true at i if and only if ψ is true at all ϕ-worlds whatever; there are no inaccessible ϕ-worlds to be left out of consideration.

Corresponding to physical necessity, and the physical strict conditional, we assign to each world i as its sphere of accessibility Si the set of all worlds where the laws of nature prevailing at i hold; so the physical strict conditional (ϕψ) is true at i if and only if ψ is true at all those ϕ-worlds where the laws prevailing at i hold.

Corresponding to a kind of time-dependent necessity we may call inevitability at time t, and its strict conditional, we assign to each world i as its sphere of accessibility the set of all worlds that are exactly like i at all times up to time t, so (ϕψ) is true at i if and only if ψ is true at all ϕ-worlds that are exactly like i up to t.

Corresponding to what we might call necessity in respect of facts of so-and-so kind, and its strict conditional, we assign to each world i as its sphere of accessibility the set of all worlds that are exactly like i in respect of all facts of so-and-so kind, so (ϕψ) is true at i if and only if ψ is true at all ϕ-worlds that are exactly like i in respect of all facts of so-and-so kind.

A degenerate case: corresponding to what we may call necessity in respect of all facts, or fatalistic necessity, we assign to each world i as its sphere of accessibility the set of all worlds that are exactly like i in all respects whatever. Since ‘all respects whatever’ includes likeness in respect of identity or nonidentity to i, i alone is like i in all respects whatever; thus each world i has as its sphere of accessibility the set {i} having i as its sole member. Then ϕ is true at i if and only if ϕ is true at i; and the fatalistic strict conditional (ϕψ) is true at i if and only if the material conditional ϕψ is true at i.

Sometimes we do not insist that each world i must belong to its own sphere of accessibility Si. Corresponding to deontic (or moral) necessity, we assign to each world i as its sphere of accessibility the set of all morally perfect worlds. Then ϕ is true at i if and only if ϕ is true at every morally perfect world. A morally imperfect world like ours does not belong to its own sphere of accessibility.

We have another degenerate case: corresponding to what I may call vacuous necessity, we assign to each world i as its sphere of accessibility the empty set, making ϕ true at i for any sentence ϕ and world i whatever.

We may compare the strictness of different strict conditionals. The more inclusive are the spheres of accessibility, the stricter is the conditional. Suppose we have necessity operators 1 and 2, corresponding to the assignment to each world i of spheres of accessibility and respectively. Then the strict conditional 2(ϕψ) is stricter at world i than 1(ϕψ) if and only if properly includes One strict conditional is stricter than another if and only if the first is stricter at every world. Note that any strict conditional is implied by any stricter conditional with the same antecedent and consequent.

Thus the logical strict conditional is stricter than any other; the material conditional is the least strict of all the conditionals that obey the constraint that every world is self-accessible; and the physical strict conditional, for instance, falls in between. The vacuous conditional is the least strict conditional of all.

It may happen, of course, that two strict conditionals are incomparable. It may be that they are incomparable at some world because neither sphere includes the other. Or they may be comparable at every world, but one may be stricter at some worlds and the other at other worlds.

Counterfactuals are related to a kind of strict conditional based on comparative similarity of possible worlds. A counterfactual is true at a world i if and only if ψ holds at certain ϕ-worlds; but certainly not all ϕ-worlds matter. ‘If kangaroos had no tails, they would topple over’ is true (or false, as the case may be) at our world, quite without regard to those possible worlds where kangaroos walk around on crutches, and stay upright that way. Those worlds are too far away from ours. What is meant by the counterfactual is that, things being pretty much as they are—the scarcity of crutches for kangaroos being pretty much as it actually is, the kangaroos’ inability to use crutches being pretty much as it actually is, and so on—if kangaroos had no tails they would topple over.

We might think it best to confine our attention to worlds where kangaroos have no tails and everything else is as it actually is; but there are no such worlds. Are we to suppose that kangaroos have no tails but that their tracks in the sand are as they actually are? Then we shall have to suppose that these tracks are produced in a way quite different from the actual way. Are we to suppose that kangaroos have no tails but that their genetic makeup is as it actually is? Then we shall have to suppose that genes control growth in a way quite different from the actual way (or else that there is something, unlike anything there actually is, that removes the tails). And so it goes; respects of similarity and difference trade off. If we try too hard for exact similarity to the actual world in one respect, we will get excessive differences in some other respect.

There is a simpler argument that there is no world where kangaroos have no tails and everything else is as it actually is. Consider all the material conditionals of the form

ϕkangaroos have tails

such that ϕ is true at the actual world. If kangaroos had no tails and everything else were as it actually is, then these conditionals would be true as they actually are, for these conditionals are part of the ‘everything else’. Also, in most cases, the antecedents would be true as they actually are, for (at least when the antecedent is irrelevant to whether kangaroos have tails) the antecedents also are part of the ‘everything else’. But then, unless the world is one where modus ponens goes haywire (so that logic itself is not as it actually is!), kangaroos do have tails there after all. I know of nothing wrong with this argument, but I admit that it looks like an unconvincing trick; so I prefer to rely on the considerations of the previous paragraph.

It therefore seems as if counterfactuals are strict conditionals corresponding to an accessibility assignment determined by similarity of worlds—overall similarity, with respects of difference balanced off somehow against respects cf similarity. Let Si , for each world i, be the set of all worlds that are similar to at least a certain fixed degree to the world i. Then the corresponding strict conditional is true at i if and only if the material conditional of its antecedent and consequent is true throughout Si; that is, if and only if the consequent holds at all antecedent-worlds similar to at least that degree to i.

If we take any one counterfactual, this will do nicely. But trouble may come if we consider several counterfactuals together. (1) ‘If I (or you, or anyone else) walked on the lawn, no harm at all would come of it; but if everyone did that, the lawn would be ruined’ (2) ‘If the USA threw its weapons into the sea tomorrow, there would be war; but if the USA and the other nuclear powers all threw their weapons into the sea tomorrow there would be peace; but if they did so without sufficient precautions against polluting the world’s fisheries there would be war; but if, after doing so, they immediately offered generous reparations for the pollution there would be peace; ....’* (3) ‘If Otto had come, it would have been a lively party; but if both Otto and Anna had come it would have been a dreary party; but if Waldo had come as well, it would have been lively; but. ...’

These sequences have the following general form. I include with each asserted counterfactual also the negated opposite, for in the cases I imagine these negated opposites also are held true.

With a little ingenuity, it seems possible to prolong such a sequence indefinitely. No one stage in the sequence refutes the theory that the counterfactual is a strict conditional based on similarity, but any two adjacent stages do. The counterfactual on the left at any stage contradicts the negated counterfactual on the right at the next stage. Take the first and second stages: no matter how the spheres of accessibility may be assigned, if ψ is true at every accessible ϕ1-world, then ψ; is true at every accessible (ϕ1 & ϕ2)-world. So if the counterfactual is any strict conditional whatever, then ϕ1 ψ implies ϕ1 & ϕ2 ψ and contradicts ~ (ϕ1 & ϕ2 ψ Likewise ϕ1& ϕ2 ~ψ implies ϕ1 & ϕ2 & ϕ3 ~ψ and contradicts ~(ϕ1 & ϕ2 & ϕ3 ~ψ), and so on down the sequence.

The left-hand counterfactuals make trouble for the theory that the counterfactual is a strict conditional, even without their negated opposites. If those at two adjacent stages both are true, then according to the theory the second is true vacuously. So are all those beyond it. Beginning at the beginning: if ψ is true at every accessible ϕ1-world but ~ψ is true at every accessible (ϕ1 & ϕ2)-world, then there must not be any accessible (ϕ1 & ϕ2)-worlds—nor any accessible (ϕ1 & ϕ2 $ & ϕ3)-worlds, nor. … Then if the lower counterfactuals are true, it is no thanks to their consequents: if a strict conditional is vacuously true, then so is any other with the same antecedent. From the premises that if Otto had come it would have been lively and that if Otto and Anna had come it would have been dreary, it follows that if Otto and Anna had come then the cow would have jumped over the moon. Since that does not follow, the counterfactual is not a strict conditional.

If we treat the counterfactual as a strict conditional based on similarity, then the best we can do for our troublesome sequences is to keep changing our minds about which such strict conditional it is. We may be able to make the two sentences at any one stage true by an appropriate choice of a sphere of accessibility based on similarity, but we must choose anew for each stage. If so, we have the situation shown in Figure 2. Suppose we have a sphere around i that is right for the first stage: ψ is true at every ϕ1-world in , and—since there are ϕ1-worlds in —it is not the case that ~ψ also is true at every ϕ1-world in . Then is wrong for the second stage. So is any sphere smaller than . But by changing our minds about the degree of similarity to i that we require, perhaps we can find a sphere that is right for the second stage. corresponds to less stringent standards of similarity than , and to a stricter conditional. (The stringency of the standards of similarity goes inversely with the strictness of the conditional. Less stringent standards of similarity bring more worlds into accessibility, making it more difficult for anything to hold at all those worlds.) is wrong for the first stage; in order to handle the second stage we had to expand the sphere of accessibility to reach some (ϕ1 & ϕ2 & ~ψ)-worlds, and these falsify the first-stage counterfactual. is wrong also for the third stage. So is any sphere smaller than . But by changing our minds once again, perhaps we can find a still larger sphere —a still less stringent standard of similarity, a still stricter conditional—that is right for the third stage. It is wrong for the second and first, however; and for the fourth, if the sequence continues. In short: it may be that for every stage of the sequence, there is a choice of strictness that is right for that stage. But as we go down the sequence, we need stricter and stricter conditionals. The choice that works at any one stage makes false all the counterfactuals at previous stages, and all the negated opposites at subsequent stages. If counterfactuals are strict conditionals we have no hope of deciding, once and for all, how strict they are.

FIGURE 2

It will not help to plead vagueness. If counterfactuals were strict conditionals based on similarity, indeed they would presumably be vague ones. The assignment of spheres of accessibility for them would be fixed only within rough limits. This might happen both because our ways of trading off respects of similarity and difference against each other are not well fixed and because the degree of overall similarity to a world i that is set as a condition of membership in the sphere of accessibility around i is not well fixed. Both sources of vagueness would tend to make some counterfactuals indefinite in truth value, since the truth value will come out differently under different equally acceptable resolutions of the vagueness. But the counterfactuals and their negated opposites in our troublesome sequence are not necessarily especially indefinite in their truth value. I think it is clear from my examples that such a sequence could consist of counterfactuals and their negated opposites all of which are as definitely true as counterfactuals ever are (except for those paragon counterfactuals in which the antecedent logically implies the consequent).

Neither will it help to plead dependence on context. If counterfactuals were vague strict conditionals, no doubt context would resolve some of the vagueness, and different contexts would sometimes resolve it differently. But our problem is not a conflict between counterfactuals in different contexts, but rather between counterfactuals in a single context. It is for this reason that I put my examples in the form of a single run-on sentence, with the counterfactuals of different stages conjoined by semicolons and ‘but’. While one context may favor a delineation of baldness on which Dudley is bald, and another may favor a delineation on which he is not, no context can favor a delineation on which he both is and is not. There is no such delineation. While one context might favor a level of strictness on which the first-stage pair in our sequence are both true, and another may favor a greater strictness on which the second-stage pair are both true, and still another may favor a still greater strictness on which the third-stage pair are both true, and so on, none can favor a strictness on which the four sentences from the pairs at two adjacent stages are all true. There is no such strictness.

It is still open to say that counterfactuals are vague strict conditionals based on similarity, and that the vagueness is resolved—the strictness is fixed—by very local context: the antecedent itself. That is not altogether wrong, but it is defeatist. It consigns to the wastebasket of contextually resolved vagueness something much more amenable to systematic analysis than most of the rest of the mess in that wastebasket.

1.3 Variably Strict Conditionals

counterfactuals are like strict conditionals based on similarity of worlds, but there is no saying how strict they are. They come in as many different strictnesses as there can be stages in my sequence of counterfactuals and their negated opposites. I suggest, therefore, that the counterfactual is not any one strict conditional, but is rather what I shall call a variably strict conditional. Any particular counterfactual is as strict, within limits, as it must be to escape vacuity, and no stricter.

Corresponding to any (constantly) strict conditional, as we have seen, there is an assignment to each world i of a single sphere of accessibility Si around i. Corresponding to a variably strict conditional, on the other hand, there must be an assignment to each world i of a set $i of spheres of accessibility around i, some larger and some smaller. Such an assignment is required to meet certain formal constraints, laid down in the following definition. We shall see later how, and to what extent, these constraints are justified.

Let $ be an assignment to each possible world i of a set $i of sets of possible worlds. Then $ is called a (centered*) system of spheres, and the members of each $i are called spheres around i, if and only if, for each world i, the following conditions hold.

(C) $i is centered on i; that is, the set {i} having i as its only member belongs to $i.
(1) $i is nested; that is, whenever S and T belong to $i, either S is included in T or T is included in S.
(2) $i is closed under unions; that is, whenever is a subset of $i and is the set of all worlds j such that j belongs to some member of S, belongs to $i.
(3) $i, is closed under (nonempty) intersections; that is, whenever is a nonempty subset of $i and is the set of all worlds j such that j belongs to every member of , belongs to $i,.

The system of spheres used in interpreting counterfactuals is meant to carry information about the comparative overall similarity of worlds. Any particular sphere around a world i is to contain just those worlds that resemble i to at least a certain degree. This degree is different for different spheres around i. The smaller the sphere, the more similar to i must a world be to fall within it. To say the same thing in purely comparative terms: whenever one world lies within some sphere around i and another world lies outside that sphere, the first world is more closely similar to i than the second. Conversely, if S is any set of worlds such that every member of S is more similar to i than any non-member of S, then S should be one of the spheres around i. (An exception: we may or may not count the set of all worlds as one of the spheres around i, although it vacuously meets the condition just given.)‡

Our four formal constraints in the definition of a centered system of spheres are justified because, if they were not met, the spheres could not very well be regarded as carrying information about comparative similarity of worlds.

(C) Surely each world i is as similar to itself as any other world is to it; therefore i should belong to every (nonempty) sphere around i. Almost as surely, no other world is quite as similar to a world i as i itself is; even if there were a world j qualitatively indiscernible from i (imagining for the moment that possible worlds are not the sort of things that obey a non-trivial law of identity of indiscernibles) we might still argue that i does, and j does not, resemble i in respect of being identical to i. Therefore some sphere around i should contain i and exclude all other worlds; that is, {i} should be a sphere around i.

(1) If some $i were not nested, we would have two spheres S and T in $i, and two worlds j and k, such that j lies within S but outside T, and k lies within T but outside S. If S and T both carried information about comparative similarity to i, then j would be more similar than k to i (because j does and k does not lie within the sphere S) but also k would be more similar than j to i (because k does and j does not lie within T). We cannot have it both ways.
(2) Suppose j does, and k does not, lie within the union of a set of spheres around i. It follows that j does, and k does not, lie within some sphere S in S, and hence that j is more similar than k to i Therefore is a set such that any world within it is more similar to i than any world outside it, and such a set should be a sphere around i.
(3) Similarly, suppose j does, and k does not, lie within the intersection of a nonempty set of spheres; then j does, and k does not, lie within some sphere S in ; so j is more similar than k to i. is a set such that any world within it is more similar toithan any world outside it, and hence should be a sphere around i.

Note that conditions (2) and (3) of closure under union and intersection are automatically satisfied when there are only finitely many spheres around i, or in the case of a finite subset of an infinite $i. If there is a biggest sphere in (one that includes all the others) it is S. If there is a smallest sphere in (one that is included in all the others) it is S. By nesting, every finite set of spheres around a world has a biggest and a smallest. But not so an infinite set: it may have bigger and bigger spheres without end, or smaller and smaller spheres without end. It would simplify things considerably if we could rule out this annoying possibility by fiat; but we shall see that such a fiat would be unjustifiable.

Condition (2) of closure under unions implies that the empty set is a sphere around each i; for in (2) I did not require to be nonempty, and by definition the union of empty is empty. To include the empty sphere is technically convenient, but unintuitive; however, it can easily be verified that the presence of the empty sphere has no effect at all on the truth conditions to be given with reference to the system of spheres.

More important, I have left it open whether or not the set of all possible worlds is to be one of the spheres around each world i; or in other words, whether or not the union $i of all spheres around i is to exhaust the set of worlds; or, in still other words, whether or not every possible world is to lie within some or other sphere around i. If $i is the set of all worlds, for each i, I will call $ universal. If not, then I regard the worlds that the spheres around i do not reach—those that lie outside $i—as being all equally similar to i, and less similar to i than any world that the spheres do reach. We will see that any such world will be left out of consideration in determining whether a counterfactual is true at i. It is as if, from the point of view of i, these remotest worlds were not possible worlds at all.